Maurice Blanchot (1907-2003)
In the Fontana Dictionary of Modern Thinkers, (1983) there are entries for Mitterand and Foucault (as well as for Marilyn Monroe), but no
entry for Maurice Blanchot, one of France's foremost post-war writers and
critics, and a thinker who has exerted a powerful influence on Foucault and many
others. From his critical writings we can deduce that this fact would not
trouble Blanchot at all; in fact, because he sees riting as autonomous, and the
outcome of a profound solitude, a biography, or a curriculum vitae, is of little
elevance for assisting a reader in coming to grips with the enigmas of a truly
literary work. In fact, Blanchot's silence on matters biographical constitutes
an important part of his literary project. For him the literary object is at one
and the same time irreducible (to psychological or sociological explanations)
and indeterminate (it is never possible to recover all of the meaning and
significance of a literary text). Whether this amounts, as Tzvetan Todorov has
argued, to a continuation of Romanticism is perhaps one of the key issues
pertaining to an understanding of Blanchot's oeuvre.
Despite some stiff competition, Blanchot who was born in 1907 and devotes his
life entirely to literature has acquired a reputation for writing some of the
most enigmatic prose in modern French. In light of the fact that he has himself
indirectly clarified some of the motivations for his literary work in his
critical writings,2 the claim is no doubt extreme. On the other hand, as a
certain force drives writing towards an unknowable centre of attraction - one
that is only dimly perceptible to the one who is writing a degree of obscurity
seems to be built into Blanchot's project. While there are good reasons for
refusing the epithet of Romanticism in Blanchot's case (Blanchot's refusal of
the notion of the author as origin being one of them), there is a much stronger
case for saying that Blanchot is a lucid proponent of artistic modernism. This
does not imply an acceptance of a particular version of the principle of
original creativity. Blanchot has indeed heeded the warning represented by the
Hegelian dialectic, where, in the end, everything will be recuperated within the
framework of Absolute Knowledge. Eventually, Hegel argues, history will come to
an end; the goal of the system will be united in the process of arriving at it.
All of Blanchot's oeuvre could be seen as a refusal to accept the basis of
Hegel's philosophy of the inevitability of the homogeneity implied in the end of
history.
From his critical writings of the 195Os, it is clear that Blanchot is opposed to
any easy appropriation of the authentically literary text. This frequently
happens, however, with few critics actually reading what they claim to have
read. Rather, they prefer to write their commentaries on the basis of readings
which set new works in pre-existing categories; when the Critic does happen to
see that a work cannot be thus interpreted, it is too late for reading; for the
critic is already an author and thus unable to become a reader. True reading,
Blanchot implies, is one that respects the literary work's singularity.
|